• POLS 844: Governing Difference,  Secessions, Partitions, State Down-sizing

    Sambanis, N. (2000) ‘Partition as a Solution to Ethnic War: An Empirical Critique of the Theoretical Literature’

    Sambanis, N. (2000) ‘Partition as a Solution to Ethnic War: An Empirical Critique of the Theoretical Literature’, World Politics 52 (4), 437-483

    1. Partition theorists have not produced operational criteria for applying their theories consistently across cases.
    2. Empirical testing could help elucidate these theoretical debates.
    3. Focus on claims that once ethnic violence starts, civil politics can only be restored if ethnic groups are demographically separated into ‘defensible enclaves’ (438) and solutions aiming to restore multi-ethnic civil politics will not work because they do not resolve existing security dilemmas (‘SD’).
    4. SDs are at heart of partition theory: when communities distrust each other, one community’s actions to increase its own security is seen as threatening to security of others.
    5. Therefore, the claim is that partition in homogenous separate regions becomes inevitable to end conflict.
    6. No proof for this has been provided.
    7. Will test three core hypotheses:
      1. Partitions facilitate post-war democratization;
      2. Partitions prevent war recurrence;
      3. Partitions significantly reduce low-level ethnic violence.
    8. Result: Partitions do not prevent recurrence of ethnic war and may not even be necessary to stop low-level ethnic violence.
    9. Criticism of partition:
      1. too limiting a solution: ethnic cooperation may be possible even after a civil war.
      2. too severe a solution: forced population movements cause tremendous human suffering.
      3. Will create undemocratic successor states: repression of residual minorities.
      4. Endorsing some partition will encourage others, leading to wars: not true; this is rare.
    10. SD ignores the fact that conflict is often due not to ethnic groups’ security needs, but to ‘predatory’ goals of their leaders; therefore, partition will not solve the SD of partitioned ethnic groups if it exacerbates ‘predatory’ incentives of predecessor states.
    11. Civil wars tend not to end in negotiated settlements, unless supported by external security guarantees that prevent predatory predecessor states from restarting wars against successor states (442).
    12. Alternative to both Partition (‘P’) and creating a new balance of power is to create a regional hegemon responsible for regional peace.
    13. Ethnic diffusion might mitigate the SD (Byman) because it reduces the possibility that a single ethnic group might become dominant (443): ‘ethnic balancing’ against threatening groups is both possible and stabilizing.
    14. “The probability of civil war drops significantly at very high levels of ethnic diversity and it is greatest in ethnically polarised societies” (443).
    15. Four key questions related to partition must be investigated:
      1. What are the main determinants of P?
      2. Does P create democratic or undemocratic states?
      3. Does P prevent war recurrence?
      4. Does P end low-level ethnic violence?
    16. Complied data set with 125 civil wars and 21 partitions.
    17. Testable hypotheses.
    18. Findings:
      1. Type of war is a significant determinant of partition: ethnicity matters for the onset of partition.
      2. As ethnic heterogeneity increases, probability of partition decreases significantly; as size of ethnic groups increase, so does likelihood of partition.
      3. Partitions are positively and significantly correlated with levels of violence; but violence may well be caused by partition itself.
      4. “Partition is more likely after identity than ideological war, after truce or rebel victory following war, in a country with large ethnic groups and little heterogeneity, and higher levels of economic development.
    19. Three critical hypotheses of P theory:
      1. Ps create successor states that are at least as democratic as predecessors: evidence unclear; more research needed.
      2. Ps reduce risk of war recurrence: evidence does not support this. Therefore, separating ethnic groups does not resolve the problem of violent ethnic antagonism.
      3. Ps reduce low-level ethnic violence after war ends: very weak evidence in favor.
    20. Ps are coerced, painful, costly, may saw seeds for future conflicts. International policy towards P must rely on rigorous, empirical testing and arguments.
    21. New Hypothesis: “The strategy of supporting ethnic diffusion by combining rather than partitioning large ethnic groups may be worth pursuing” after a civil war: “If borders can be credibly and securely redrawn, then combining several large ethnic groups in a larger multiethnic state may reduce the probability of new wars” (479).
    22. “Partition, as we have seen, does not help reduce the risk of war recurrence. Partitions are in fact positively (though not significantly) associated with recurrence of ethnic war. The probability of a new war rises in tandem with the human toll of the previous war and with non-decisive outcomes to the war” (480).
    23. “Negotiated settlements, a strong government army, and a lengthy previous war all reduce the probability of war recurrence” (481).
    24. “To reduce residual violence, it is important to prevent war recurrence, as patterns of large-scale violence over time seem to encourage lower-level violence” (481).
    25. “Strategies to support the government’s prewar institutions and its military may also achieve peace, but they may do so at the expense of justice” (481).
    26. Empirically-derived strategy for resolving ethnic war: “This strategy demands action by the international community, which must promote democracy as its number one conflict-prevention strategy. If violence does erupt, its priority should be to facilitate a negotiated settlement, as well as to integrate and downsize the government’s military… If border redefinition is a viable option – and it should be an option only if it does not assist one party at the expense of another – then ethnic integration rather than ethnic partition may be a winning strategy. In addition to having the potential for greater success than partition, this strategy is also not loaded with subjective and arbitrary assumptions about the necessity for ethnically pure states and about the futility of interethnic cooperation” (481).
    27. “On average, partition may be an impossible solution to ethnic civil war” (482).

  • POLS 844: Governing Difference,  Secessions, Partitions, State Down-sizing

    Kumar, R. (1997) “The Troubled History of Partition’

    Kumar, R. (1997) “The Troubled History of Partition’, Foreign Affairs 76 (1) (Jan./Feb. 1997), 22-34.

    1. 1995 Dayton Peace Accord: a partition agreement with an exit clause for outside powers.
    2. Claim that partitions as solutions to ethnic conflicts save lives, safeguard rights of contending ethnic groups through intervention of impartial outside power, and create homogenous territories through population transfers.
    3. Instead of doing so, partitions “fomented further violence and forced mass migration” (24).
    4. Partition assumes irreconcilable ethnic identities and capacity to separate ethnic groups.
    5. Usually, partitions are “driven by considerations extraneous to the needs and desires of the people displaced” and “end up stimulating further and even new conflict” (26).
    6. Case studies of Cyprus, Palestine, Northern Ireland, India, Bosnia show that partitions are seen as temporary solutions to crises; however, once implemented “ethnic partitions have never been reversed; their implementation has inexorably driven communities further apart”. (33).
    7. Ethnic partition can hamper development of postwar economies.
    8. “Divide and Quit” approach rarely works: it turns into “Divide and Be forced to stay” (34).
    9. “Investment in reintegration may be discovered as the easier route to withdrawal.” (34)
  • POLS 844: Governing Difference,  Secessions, Partitions, State Down-sizing

    Horowitz, D.L. (2003) ‘The Cracked Foundations of the Right to Secede’

    Horowitz, D.L. (2003) ‘The Cracked Foundations of the Right to Secede’, Journal of Democracy 14 (2), 5-17.

    1. Two international legal developments in regulation of conflict and warfare between ethnic groups:
      1. Tribunals to punish genocide and crimes against humanity;
      2. Elaboration of various doctrines of human rights, including a possible right of ethnic groups to secede.
    2. Such a right is ill-considered and dangerous.
    3. Certain theorists see secession as answer to problems of ethnic conflict and violence; that is wrong: it is likely to make such problems worse.
    4. Secession does not create homogenous successor states or reduce conflict, violence, or minority oppression in successor states (5-6).
    5. Minorities’ condition can best be improved by devising institutions to increase their satisfaction within existing states.
    6. “Partition can be accomplished reluctantly, as a matter of prudence, without recognizing a right to secede” 96).
    7. Atlantic Charter, 1941: self-determination limited to peoples living under foreign domination, resulting in decolonization.
    8. From the end of WWII to end of Cold War territorial boundaries were remarkably stable.
    9. After the end of the Cold War boundaries became less stable. Badinter Commission on Yugoslavia legitimised breakup of this federation.
    10. Various theories of self-determination leading to secession:
      1. An integral right of peoples to be free of authoritarian oppression: right to live under a democratic regime;
      2. Right of people in general of with common group characteristics to choose with whom they wish to associate politically – although collective identity fluctuates;
      3. Remedial right: last-ditch response to discrimination or oppression by central government;
      4. All assume secession can result in homogenous successor states or at least ones that will guarantee minority rights.
    11. Treatment of minorities in new states will not improve if minorities were not respected in undivided state.
    12. “Secession merely proliferates the arenas in which the problem of intergroup political accommodation must be faced” (9).
    13. Secession encourages the former minority, now a majority, to cleanse the secessionist state of its own minorities and induces the rump state to do the same.
    14. There are no truly natural boundaries that secession can institutionalise.
    15. Secessions and partitions convert domestic ethnic disputes into more dangerous international ones and trigger irredentist claims that often are followed by ethnic cleansing.
    16. A right to secede will undermine efforts to achieve interethnic accommodation within states (10).
    17. Devolution efforts are most effectively undermined by a right, recognised under international law, to secession.
    18. “A right to secession effectively advantages militant members of ethnic groups at the expense of conciliators.” (11)
    19. A right to secession grounded in extreme oppression of minorities derives from an alleged commitment of international law to democracy. Such a commitment is tenuous at best.
    20. Self-determination for peoples or groups within a state is to be achieved by participation in its constitutional system, on the basis of respect for its territorial integrity.
    21. Secession is an anti-state movement and undermines the very foundation of current international legal order – state sovereignty.
    22. Solution is to foster interethnic accommodation within states, through institutions that can mitigate conflict:
      1. Consociational democracy: neglect of democratic opposition and propensity for excessively limited government and immobilism; it is attractive to minorities, not majorities.
      2. Use of political incentives to encourage ethnic moderation: electoral systems capable of inducing moderate behaviour by politicians.
    23. Political engineering can work in specific circumstances, but is no panacea.
    24. “Efforts at conciliation will not be helped by providing either a liberal or constrained right to secede” (15).
  • POLS 844: Governing Difference,  Secessions, Partitions, State Down-sizing

    O’Leary, B. (2016) ‘Debating Partition’

    O’Leary, B. (2016) ‘Debating Partition’, K. Cordell and S. Wolff, eds., The Routledge Handbook of Ethnic Conflict, 2.ed., London, Routledge, 138-154.

    1. Partition: “a fresh political border cut through at least one community’s national homeland with the goal of resolving conflict” (138).
    2. Key political and moral arguments to resolve antagonisms through partition:
      1. Historicist: partition is inevitable once ethnic conflicts pass a certain threshold. It is seen as both informed and realistic, but record shows that there can be peace without separation.
      2. Last resort: if alternative strategies fail, partition should be chosen to avoid genocide or large-scale ethnic expulsions.
      3. Net benefit: “partition should be chosen when, on balance, it offers a better prospect of conflict reduction than maintaining the existing borders”. It is desirable in its own right, not just as last resort. (139).
      4. Better tomorrow: without partition there will be more conflict and conflict recurrence; therefore, after partition parties will conduct themselves better.
      5. Realist rigour: partition must lead to radical demographic restructuring, to reduce military and political significance of new minorities.
    3. They all suggest that “it is foolish to insist on maintaining unviable multinational polities” (141).
    4. Modalities:
      1. Proceduralists: consultations with affected parties to achieve reciprocal consent on new border: deploy fairness and feasibility requirements. A. Lijphart set requirements for a fair partition: negotiated not imposed; fair division of land and resources; results in substantially less plural independent states.
      2. Paternalists: local parties cannot reasonably agree, therefore a sufficiently powerful outsider must determine partition that will be durable and reduce conflict fast.
    5. Anti-partitionist arguments share views of partitions as perverse, of jeopardising existing relationships, and of impossibility of achieving fair partitions:
      1. Rejection of rupturing of national unity: majority of original state opposes secession as violation of its right to self-determination, seen as only in interest of privileged elites.
      2. Constructive possibility of bi- and multi-nationalism: pluri-national arrangements must be properly exhausted before partition is considered genuinely as a last resort. Often, minority leaders refuse or block all other options.
      3. Practical impossibility of just partitions:
        1. a number of key difficulties that a boundary commission would need to decide:
          • Which should be the units around which new boundaries should be drawn?
          • Should there be subunit optouts?
          • How should units’ preferences be determined?
          • Should local popular preferences be considered just one criterion to be balanced among others?
          • Should non-preferential factors be considered in designing new borders, and should local popular preferences be subordinated thereto – and who should decide this?
          • Should there be constitutional amendments to ratify proposals and referendums, and should there be provisions for their subsequent revision?
        2. “partitions are perverse: they achieve exactly the opposite of what they nominally intend” (147).
        3. Kaufmann (1998) is wrong when he argues that partition reduced violence in his 4 case-studies. He shows “it is easy to slip from a defense of partition as a last resort to tacit support for ethnic expulsions” (148).
        4. Partitions often lead to post-partition wars., creating inter-state ‘security dilemmas’.
      4. Elusive mirage of homogenization without expulsion:
        1. Partition alone is unlikely to create desired levels of homogenization.
        2. Assimilation, expulsion, even genocide will follow.
        3. “Partitions are never enough for rigorous homogenizers.” (149)
        4. “Partitions without comprehensive expulsions generate two kinds of orphaned minorities: former prospective majorities, and formerly dominant minorities” (149). They both may become part of irredentist movements or campaign for further partitions.
      5. Damage to successor states:
        1. Partitions generate new inter-state security crises and cause significant economic disruption by disturbing established monetary and exchange networks, increasing transaction costs, protectionism and border-related criminal activity.
        2. Post-partition states have functional and infrastructural interests that leads them to consider cross-border cooperation or confederal arrangements that put into question the need for partition itself.
        3. Usually, one of the two post-partition states is significantly disadvantaged and significantly underperforms.
      6. Failure to make a clean or elegant cut:
        1. Post-partitionists’ maps bleed and “do not look good” (149).
        2. New borders are usually less compact and create adverse security and transport connections.
    6. Anti-partitionists’ arguments are more compelling judged by realistic, political and moral criteria and are endorsed by international law.
    7. “Give power-sharing a chance” (151): complex power-sharing settlements are possible even after protracted ethno-national wars.
    8. Partitions deserve their poor press, as they do not generate better security environments and are biased towards privileged or dominant minorities.
    9. Post-partition arrangements are worse than predicted for at least one successor state.
    10. “Prudence therefore mandates opposing partition as a tool of international public policy-making, and placing the burden of proof on its advocates” 152.
    11. Hard to find a good 20th-century partition.
    12. Implementing a new border destabilizes inter-group relations in ways that may take generations to repair. Secessions harden existing administrative borders and may be easier to accomplish.
  • POLS 844: Governing Difference,  Secessions, Partitions, State Down-sizing

    Horowitz, D.L. (2015) ‘Irredentas and secessions: Adjacent phenomena, neglected connections’

    Horowitz, D.L. (2015) ‘Irredentas and secessions: Adjacent phenomena, neglected connections’, in K. Cordell and S. Wolff, eds. The Routledge Handbook of Ethnic Conflict, 2.ed., London, Routledge, 155-164.

    1. Secessions and irredentas have traditionally not been treated together, but they are deeply interconnected: the strength of one movement is related to the fact that the other may well rise – they are plausible alternatives to each other.
    2. Secession: attempt by an ethnic group claiming a homeland to withdraw with its territory from the authority of a larger state of which it is part (155).
    3. Irredentism: a movement by members of an ethnic group in one state to retrieve ethnically kindred people and their territory across borders.
    4. Both secession and irredentism contain various levels of intensity and various strategies (irredentism: incorporation into another state; creation of a new state from various irredentist groups).
    5. Secession: subtracting from an existing state; Irredentism: subtracting from one state and adding to another.
    6. There have been very few irredentas in postcolonial states, but many secessionist movements.
    7. Some international border disputes have no ethnic component; others contain compact ethnic groups that nevertheless do not dominate their region.
    8. When faced with a choice between the two, groups find secession the more satisfying choice. “Indeed, the potential for irredentism may increase the frequency and strength of secession, but not vice-versa” (157).
    9. Three issues that connect S and I:
      1. Convertibility of S and I:
        1. violence is convertible from one to the other;
        2. so is mutability of ethnic group claims and of trans-border affinities.
        3. State policies towards both also change over time: they tend to be inconstant towards I, which drives groups towards S.
        4. Ethnic affinity in one state may not extend to the irredentist group, also favoring S.
      2. Relative frequency of S and I:
        1. Irredentist action by the potential retrieving state is uncommon.
        2. Aid to S movements can be strategically terminated; aid to I movements cannot because they are underpinned by “an ideology of common fate” that does not lend itself to abrupt termination (160).
        3. In turn, irredentist groups find retrieval by another state undesirable because of their own personal interests as political leaders. S given them a better access to power, whilst I allows them to be challenged by leaders of retrieving state.
        4. Retrieving state itself may be heterogenous.
        5. Multiple secessions to build a new state (eg. Kurdistan) is almost impossible.
        6. In practice, even groups that have theoretically an I option do not really have it in practice and end up opting for S.
        7. “In short, all else being equal, the fewer the irredentas, the larger the number of secessionist movements” (161).
      3. Relative strength of S and I:
        1. Relative strength of a movement I affected by whether they chose S or I and whether the other is also available.
        2. States that are reluctant to engage in I claims may assist groups to achieve S (India / Bangladesh).
    10. When will an ethnoterritorial separatism movement take S or I courses? It’s a strategic choice based on calculations of rational interest.
    11. However, emotional factors cannot be discounted (eg. Ethnic affinity): secession movements continue to arise although secession almost always fails.
  • POLS 844: Governing Difference,  Secessions, Partitions, State Down-sizing

    McGarry, J. (1998) ‘Orphans of Secession: National Pluralism in Secessionist Regions and Post-Secessionist States’

    McGarry, J. (1998) ‘Orphans of Secession: National Pluralism in Secessionist Regions and Post-Secessionist States’, in M. Moore, ed., National Self-Determination and Secession, Oxford, OUP, 216-28.

    1. National pluralism problem: many states, even while respecting individual rights, do not treat all national groups with equal respect.
    2. ‘New liberalism’ school attempts to remedy this, but do not extend their analysis to debate on self-determination and secession: still offer a restrictive view of right to secession (eg. A. Buchanan: only if group is victim of injustice). They do not consider the nationalist basis of most secession movements (216)
    3. Neither do they think adequately about national pluralism in post-secession states, even when they recognize a broader right to self-determination (eg. D. Philpott: right to self-determination, including secession, grounded in expression of autonomy).
    4. Not helpful to elaborate theoretical principles that make abstraction from national diversity, diversity of seceding area, majority – minority relations, type of existent group identities, which are all critical to each specific secession case.
    5. Problems involved in governing in post-secession states rooted in fact that these regions were seriously divided on the secession project. The new states are probably just as heterogenous as predecessors and just as likely to abuse their own minorities and engage in conflict.
    6. Solution: move away from nation-state model and towards that of a ‘multinational state’ in which all groups are treated equally. “[T]he principle of equal treatment involves moving away from idea of independent states and embracing transborder or supra-state political institutions” (217).
    7. Secessionism is usually highly contested not just by remainder state but also within secessionist region, by local ethnic minorities, against the largest regional ethnic group that achieved secession.
    8. Secessions usually occur along administrative rather than national lines; therefore, national heterogeneity continues. Administrative boundaries did not create homogenous subunits on purpose, to better “control minority passions” (219).
    9. Sometimes ethnic minorities do support secession (eg. Baltic Countries and Ukraine in former USSR). In other cases opposition can come even from large sections of local ethnic majority against the elite driving the project.
    10. Conclusion: “demands of these groups for autonomy can be satisfied short of secession, and that if secession is to occur, it is unlikely that there will be a consensus behind it”. This is because “[o]utside of polarized conflict zones, individuals frequently have nestled identities, and feel part of several communities simultaneously” (220).
    11. In many cases, “secession does not solve the problem of national diversity: it merely places it in a different state context.”
    12. New states are often ‘nationalizing states’ seeking to promote interests of national majorities (language, culture, symbols) at the expense of their own minorities (Brubaker).
    13. Most new minorities do not revolt; many migrate back to the rump state where they are in the majority. Those who remain mobilize to secure their individual and group rights.
    14. Members with dual identities accept the new state but “regret the passing of the old” (222).
    15. Two key issues arise out of attempt to reconcile nationally-defined self-determination with liberal values of equal respect and individual autonomy:
      1. Do these dynamics, present especially in Eastern Europe, apply to Western Europe and North America as well? There is no clear East-West dichotomy: cases are rather on a continuum, depending on their specific circumstances (eg. Quebec has its own minorities opposed to secession that are highly mobilized).
      2. Is the focus on the pre-and post-secession periods an unfair context for theorizing, rather than taking a longer-term approach to allow identities to adjust to the new state? Conditions which produce conflict during state formation may be durable (eg. Northern Ireland, Israel, Romania). Triadic Nexus will continue to evolve in a vicious circle of conflict (new states worry about minority revols and frontiers security; minorities continue to withhold their loyalty; neighboring states continue irredentist claims).
    16. Similar problems may continue in rump states as well, where remaining minorities may be subjected to ‘nationalizing projects’ of remaining majority (eg. Catholics in Northern Ireland).
    17. Need to address causes of minority discontent before support for secession reaches a tipping point because the original state continues behaving like a nation-state with only one nation. Timely and genuine decentralization often effectively addresses the causes of such grievances. Extensive decentralization is consistent with state unity.
    18. Arrangements should be also made for minorities to be represented in central governments, through partnership strategies resulting in power-sharing regimes.
    19. Nationalizing states and even liberal nation-states are not suitable frameworks for this: need to develop institutions based on accommodating all national groups.
    20. Breakaway states should seem to win support from their own minorities by adopting similar decentralist and consociationalist strategies.
    21. “The appropriate way to address these problems of parallel and overlapping national loyalties is to move beyond the notion of traditional ‘Westphalian-style’ independent states and construct supra-state partnerships and institutions” (227).
    22. “Such accommodation of minority nations is, however, very much the ideal, and rarely the practice” (228).
  • POLS 844: Governing Difference,  Secessions, Partitions, State Down-sizing

    Coggins, B.R. (2011) ‘The History of Secession: An Overview’

    Coggins, B.R. (2011) ‘The History of Secession: An Overview’, in A. Pavkovic and P. Radan, The Ashgate Research Companion to Secession, London, Routledge, 24-43.

    1. Macro-historical approach: secessionism across time.
    2. Rise of nation-state, self-determination, nationalism in 16th and 17th centuries required rulers to develop a compelling national myth to legitimise their rule in order to minimise both internal and external challenges.
    3. By middle of 19th century, nationalism took two main forms: civic and ethnic.
    4. “Ethnic nationalism fractured multinational empires and the tension between national self-determination and state integrity grew steadily throughout the 20th century” (25).
    5. After WWII, “nationalists demanded that national identity be the presumptive basis for self-determination, sovereignty and membership in the international society of states” (26)
    6. Jennings: “let the people decide” seems reasonable but is in fact ridiculous because “the people cannot decide until someone decides ‘who the people are’” (26).
    7. The international system went from 25 states in 1816 to 194 in 2008.
    8. Secessionism was encouraged by President W. Wilson’s 14 points after WWI setting out a programme of national self-determination requiring a state for each nation.
    9. After WWII, anti-colonial secession exploded in the global South, legitimised and managed by the UN.
    10. Secessions arising out of anti-colonial movements and emerging from disintegrating host states usually succeeded and were recognised; most others were not.
    11. Most secessionist movements are predisposed to violence and have disastrous consequences for host states.
    12. National communities asking for self-determination are branded as internal enemies by the host state and are at risk of violence because they begin from a position of weakness: balance of power between the two means that violence favors the host.
    13. Leaders of secessionist movements stand to gain wealth, prestige, power and lifestyle upgrade if successful.
    14. Few states have ever included legal provisions for secession in their constitutions, and only a few more explicitly outlaw secession: most leave it legally ambiguous. But many secessionist movements are non-violent and end up in independence.
    15. Common tactic is formation of independentist parties advocating secession.
    16. Enduring characteristics of secession:
      1. Statehood remains a valuable commodity;
      2. Third-party states and international institutions play an influential role in secessionist conflicts, with international recognition as a sovereign state and UN membership being the ultimate prize;
      3. UN maintains that right to self-determination does not imply right to secession in order to avoid violent conflicts and wars; therefore no legal developments regarding secession have taken place over past six decades. Conditions under which secession might be deemed acceptable or justified remain unclear and can only be deduced from precedents.
      4. “Without an international consensus regarding secessionist norms, most conflicts will drag on or reach stalemates only to reignite because foreign capitals will not unanimously ratify battlefield outcomes or compel negotiated compromises between parties” (40).

  • Expulsions,  POLS 844: Governing Difference

    Mann, M. (2005) The Dark Side of Democracy: Explaining Ethnic Cleansing

    Mann, M. (2005) The Dark Side of Democracy: Explaining Ethnic Cleansing. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

    Chapter 1: The Argument

    • Study of murderous ethnic cleansing (MEC) and genocide: eight general theses, from micro to macro:
    1. MC is modern: the dark side of democracy. It results from politicized nationalism: conflation of demos (citizens) and ethnos (ethnic group) that limit it and exclude ‘others’.
      1. MEC results from organic conceptions of nation and state than encourage it.
      2. Settler democracies have been truly murderous.
      3. Regimes newly embarked on democratization are more likely to commit MEC than stable authoritarian regimes.
      4. Stable institutionalised democracies are less likely to commit MEC than both above.
      5. Regimes perpetrating MEC are never democratic: “The dark side of democracy is the perversion through time of either liberal or socialist ideas of democracy” (4).
    2. Ethnic hostility rises when ethnicity trumps class as the main form of social stratification, in the process capturing and channelling classlike sentiments towards ethnonationalism.
      1. Ethnic and class conflict infuse each other: one ethnic group must be seen as exploiting the other for ethnic conflict to develop.
    3. Danger zone of MEC is reached when:
      1. Movements claiming to represent old ethnic groups claim their own state over all or part of same territory;
      2. This claim seems to have substantial legitimacy and chance of being implemented.
    4. MEC is reached when:
      1. Less powerful side in encouraged to fight rather than submit by believing it has outside help;
      2. Stronger side believes it has the military power and ideological legitimacy to force through its cleansed state at little physical or moral risk to itself.
    5. MEC occurs when state has been factionalised and radicalised amid an unstable geopolitical environment usually leading to war.
    6. MEC is rarely the initial intent of perpetrators: eventually perpetrated deliberately, but the route to deliberation is usually circuitous.
    7. Three main levels of perpetrator:
      1. Radical elites running party-states;
      2. Bands of militants forming violent paramilitaries;
      3. Core constituencies providing mass support.
    8. Ordinary people are brought by normal social structures into committing MEC, and their motives are much more mundane.
    • Defining terms: Ethnicity, nation, ethnic cleansing
    1. Ethnicity is not objective: macro-ethnicities are socially constructed. It is a group that defines itself or is defined by others as sharing common descent and culture.
    2. Ethnic cleansing is removal by members of one such group of members of another such group from a locality they consider their own.
    3. Nation is such a group that has political consciousness and claims political rights in a given territory.
    4. Nation-state results when such a group has its own sovereign state.
    5. Multicultural states try to ignore ethnicity or to manage it through various constitutional methods (confederal, consociational). Toleration is a minimum standard.
    6. Increasingly violent methods of coercion and production of a cleansed state:
      1. Voluntary assimilation;
      2. Discrimination;
      3. Segregation;
      4. Cultural suppression;
      5. Selective policed repression;
      6. General policed repression;
      7. Mistaken policies whose unintended consequences are mass deaths;
      8. Ethnocide: unintended wiping out of a group and its culture;
      9. Exemplary repression;
      10. Forced conversion;
      11. Politicide: target is entire actual / potential leadership of a victimized group;
      12. Classicide: intended mass killings of entire social classes;
      13. Genocide (R. Lemkin, 1944).
    • Why does MEC occur? Why does it turn ‘really nasty’ in only a few cases?
    • Rival Approaches to Ethnic Cleansing
    1. Primitive throwback (primitivism);
    2. old ethnic rivalries (perennialism);
    3. Modern conflation of political ideals and ideologies (ethnosymbolism).
    • Perpetrators: Nationalist Masses or Authoritarian Elites?
    1. Two views dominate: perpetrators are either whole ethnic groups or state elites.
    2. Whole ethnic groups never act collectively: individual members of core constituencies do – they also practice in-group policing.
    3. “Once an ethnic identity is socially constructed, it may engender deep and long-lasting sentiments such that it becomes institutionalized, even structural” (21).
    4. Radical elites, usually state elites are most usually blamed of MEC.
    5. Authoritarian regimes are better than democratizing ones at damping down ethnic tensions unless these are securely institutionalized.
    6. Party-states resting on mobilised mass movements are particularly prone to MEC through “unpredictable combinations of top-down bottom-up, and sideways-violent pressures that lead to the worst atrocities” (23).
    7. Factionalized and radicalised states are most dangerous for MEC, which is almost always led by state elites.
    • Rational, Emotional, or Normative Perpetrators?
    1. Rational choice theory is pervasive, but cannot explain emotions.
    2. Three ways in which war and violence seem rational (but are not):
      1. Security dilemma;
      2. Commitment problem;
      3. Information failure.
    3. All three presuppose norms, values, identity formation; tend to assume that ethnic group identities and rivalries already exist.
    4. Max Weber: four main types of human action:
      1. Instrumentally rational action;
      2. Habitual action;
      3. Affectual action;
      4. Value-rational action
    • Perpetrators’ Motives: Ordinary People or Fanatics?

    Nine common motives for MEC:

    1. Ideological killers;
    2. Bigoted killers;
    3. Violent killers;
    4. Fearful killers;
    5. Careerist killers;
    6. Materialist killers;
    7. Disciplined killers;
    8. Comradely killers;
    9. Bureaucratic killers.
    • Causal Model: The Sources of Social Power

    Four sources of social power:

    1. Ideological power: partially private and substantially voluntary.
    2. Economic power: market choices.
    3. Military power: institutionalised and kept away from every-day-life.
    4. Political power: centralized, territorial regulation of social life. It is inherently territorial, authoritative, monopolistic. Political power relations are ultimately decisive in causing MEC.

    Chapter 2: Ethnic Cleansing in Former Times

    1. In premodern states class usually trumped ethnicity – therefore, there was little MEC.
    2. People were killed for where, not who they were: murder to cleanse particular identities is modern.
    3. This began to change with the rise of monotheistic salvation religions. Full macro-ethnicity emerged later – in modern times, and with it the potential for MEC.
    4. Military power created most large states in history. Monarchies dominated political power, centered on regional courts, detracting from macro-ethnicity encompassing entire states.
    5. Assyrians specialised in deportations, but not MEC. They eliminated troublesome states, not peoples.
    6. “Macro-ethnicity and ethnic cleansing were rare in ancient times. Larger societies were ruled through class-bound lateral aristocratic assimilation. Conquered elites were assimilated into the cultural identity of the new rulers so that macro-ethnic identities were limited by class. There was massive violence, but it was almost never directed at cleaning whole peoples” (41).
    7. With monotheism, states became ‘defenders of the faith’.
    8. Christianity became the least tolerant of the world’s salvation religions: it practiced religious cleansing – targeting Christian heretics, Muslims, Jews, lepers.
    9. By the 16th century people, nation, sovereignty and state were becoming fused in Western Europe.
    10.  Ethnic cleansing remained rare, unlike religious cleansing.
    11. Post-reconquista Spain (1492) became laboratory of “total religious cleansing, becoming more ethnic as it proceeded” with expulsion of Jews and Moors: “a unique bridge to modernity” (48)
    12.  1648 Treaty of Westphalia: Cuius regio, eius religio. No foreign aid to religious minorities any longer. “Cleansing was shifting from a religious to a national base, because the soul was becoming partly nationalized” (49): first Spain, then Western Europe, then Eastern Europe.
    13. Cromwell in Ireland practiced forced expulsions and land expropriations in the mid-17th century; Settlement Act of 1652 enshrined this into law. 15% of the Irish population died during two decades of warfare, primarily from malnutrition and disease.
    14. Historically, cleansing was systematic, but not murderous cleansing; there was no relationship between religious cleansing and regime form. It ended when almost all states became about 80% mono-religious (53).
    15. Summary: “[E]thnic cleansing was uncommon since macro-ethnicity was also uncommon. Ethnicity rarely conquered distance or class. But as salvation religions spread, religion began to cut across class and other boundaries, leading to protonational democratization and cleansing of the souls. Yet secular matters remained dominated by class and other axes of stratification. And with religious cleansing achieved, things seemed to be improving in Europe” (54).

    Chapter 3: Two Versions of “We The People”

    1. ‘People should rule’ rooted in US Declaration of Independence. Today, this legitimates most modern states and is considered to be “a good and moral collectivity” (55).
    2. Two different kinds of people can be distinguished: stratified and organic.
    3. Stratified:
      1. state as mediator;
      2. class-dominated,
      3. people as plural, shaped by contending interests institutionalised in political parties.
      4. voluntary assimilation into dominant linguistic group: no states were mono-ethnic.
      5. national identities only reached lowest classes in European states in mid- to late-19th century: the nation was born very late! (60)
      6. each country blended class and ethnicity in different ways.
      7. Violent cleansing was confined to Europe’s peripheries (Scotland, Ireland).
    4. Organic:
      1. Three differences led to organic rather than liberal conceptions of nation-state:
        1. Democracy appeared later – infused with idea that the whole people must rule; enhanced executive /statist powers and ideologies beyond liberal levels.
        2. State becomes “the bearer of a moral project” (62) and is more active for its citizens.
        3. Region was dominated by multiethnic dynastic empires, each dependent on elites of a single imperial ethnicity that divided, ruled and often discriminated against some minorities: imperial vs. proletarian ethnic conflicts.
      2. Organic conception of people and state: the people was one and indivisible, united, integral (63). “Class conflict and sectional interests were not to be compromised, but transcended, and displaced onto international conflict” (63). This generated ideal of transcendent nation and state, fueling “security dilemma” of dominant and subordinate ethnicities.
      3. Two potential vices:
        1. Can lead from democracy to authoritarian statism;
        2. Encourages notion that minority communities and political opponents can be excluded from full membership in the nation.
      4. Core beliefs:
        1. Enduring unique national character or soul;
        2. Right to a state that would express this;
        3. Right to exclude those with different characters who would weaken the nation.
    5. WWI escalated organic nationalism (ON) in central and eastern Europe.
    6. Rightist ideology embraced ON and idea of ‘cleansing’ the nation by resettlement (voluntary or coerced).
    7. Woodrow Wilson’s doctrine of national self-determination confused liberal and organic views of the nation and promised “democracy for each majority nationality”: he “believed that it was sufficient to create unitary nation-states with constitutionally-enshrined rights” (67).
    8. For a minority, there were four possibilities in an ON:
      1. Revision of frontiers to minimize nationalities;
      2. Emigration and population exchange;
      3. Physical slaughter;
      4. Constitutional changes away from nation-state form.
    9. Result was discrimination against minorities, coerced emigration, large refugee flows (10 million European refugees by 1926).
    10.  Citizenship was now identified with ethnicity; minority members were second-class citizens.
    11. Brubaker’s ‘Triadic Nexus’ of actors: national minorities, nationalizing state, kin-state.
    12. Respectable conservatives were moving towards the ON model between the two WWs and mobilizing people behind nationalism, whilst denouncing leftists as enemies of the nation.
    13.  Geopolitics played a moderating role because almost every national minority was a majority in another state; but if the balance were upset, all minorities could suffer.
    14.  The combination of ON and the ideals of freedom, self-determination and representative democracy became ‘the dark side of democracy’, leading to vision of ethnically homogenous states grounded in ‘scientific racism’.
    15.  Genocide emerges out of this tradition of modern science, modern politics, modern society.

    Chapter 17: Combating Ethnic Cleansing in the World Today

    • Eight Theses Reconsidered
    1. Murderous cleansing has been modern – the perverted dark side of democracy, where demos and ethnos are merged.
    2. Where successful, such movements trump class divisions.
    3. Conflicts arise where two old ethnic groups make legitimate and credible political claims to the same territory.
    4. Mass murder requires either a minority emboldened to fight by outside help, or a majority with the power to creates at present its own cleansed state without much physical moral or physical risk to itself.
    5. Faction-ridden, radicalised states replace conciliation with repression and are assisted by external geopolitical pressures, usually war.
    6. MEC is rarely the original intent of the perpetrators.
    7. MEC perpetrators arise from complex interactions between leaders, militants, and masses, drawn predominantly from core constituencies favoring violent ethnonationalism. “Leaders are always the most important agents” (504).
    8. Perpetrators are driven by motives found among ordinary people participating in mundane social movements, who believe in their cause and in the ends justifying the means. Three main ideological components can be detected: extreme nationalism, extreme statism, endorsement of violence.
    • Ethnic Cleansing Declined in the North but Revived in the Global South
    1. “The geopolitical environment of the northern peripheries is no longer supportive of murderous cleansing” (509).
    2. Today, all MEC takes place in the global South, marked by the spread of the ideal of the nation-state that conjoins ethnos and demos into one ‘people’.
    3. Elections become ethnic censuses, as ethnicity now trumps class.
    4. The world is polarised between a Northern zone of peace and Southern zone of turmoil.
    5. The rise of fundamentalism has weakened secularism, liberalism, and socialism.
    6. These trends set the stage for rise of ethnic-religious conflict across the South.
    7. Ethnocracy: a demos only for the ethnos. (519).
    8. Struggles are not mainly between faiths, but within faiths, between secular and sacred conception of ‘democracy’ and ‘people’, often resulting in a politicization of religion into rival claims to sovereignty over the same territory.
    • Policy Implications
    1. Eight theses identify circumstances in which MEC occurs and processes whereby it unfolds. Liberal, tolerant democracies are not inevitable outcome of modernity. Democracy’s dark side is organic and exclusionary, dangerous for minorities.
    2. We must engage with the world as it is and identify early warning signals of ethnic conflict – although exact prediction is not possible.
    3. Rival plausible and achievable claims to political sovereignty spell difficulties, deriving from some past history of sovereignty and some recent continuity of claim (523).
    4. Most minority movements could be satisfied with wider autonomy within existing boundaries, on confederal or consociational models.
    5. Mere liberal guarantees of individual rights are inadequate: “Individual and group-based conceptions of rights are both necessary” (524).
    6. These must be supplemented by collective guarantees of minority rights, policed by international agencies.
    7. Neoliberal ideology enable inequalities to acquire ethnic overtones, thus encouraging “ethnic conflict between proletarian and imperial ethnic groups” (526).
    8. Whilst ethnonationalism has grown ever stronger in the world and acquired global legitimacy, “[w]e are a long way from an international regime capable of enforcing global norms” against MEC (527). International courts or tribunals are ill equipped to deal with MEC claims involving thousands of offenders.
    9. Ethnic cleansing is essentially modern, the dark side of democracy, but is NOT a necessary feature of the human condition; nor does ethnicity always trump other less violent bases of social organization.
    10. Although we can now recognise circumstances in which ethnic cleansing threatens danger and then goes over the brink into mass murder and devise solutions to prevent this from actually occurring, “at present we lack the will to commit resources to those solutions in the South of the world.” (529).

  • Expulsions,  POLS 844: Governing Difference

    Zolberg, A.R. (1983) ‘The Formation of New States as a Refugee-Generating Process’

    Zolberg, A.R. (1983) ‘The Formation of New States as a Refugee-Generating Process’, The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 467, 24-38.

    1. Refugees: “migratory segment of a larger group of victims, singled out for the wilful exercise of extraordinary malevolence on the part of their state of residence” (24).
    2. Persecuted on grounds of political opinion / activity, or because of ascriptive characteristics.
    3. Result of secular transformation of empires into. Nation-states.
    4. Particularly acute in 3. World.
    5. Migration is viewed as an economic phenomenon; refugee flows are primarily political – result of internal upheavals and changes.
    6. Persecutor is the state – either directly or by indirection or both.
    7. For political persecution – illiberal states are responsible.
    8. Ascriptive persecutions result in massive refugee flows and account for current refugee crisis.
    9. Question: “Under what conditions do states select certain categories of population as targets for persecution, expelling them outright or creating conditions that provoke them into risky flight?” (27)
    10. Hannah Arendt: formation of nation-states leads to transformation of from human rights tradition to nationally guaranteed rights because “only nationals could be citizens” (28).
    11. A “yawning gap between the formula and social realities” developed.
    12. Two groups emerged who lost their human rights: the minorities and the stateless, resulting from “the inexorable conquest of the state by the nation” (29).
    13. “During the interwar period, denationalization became a powerful weapon of totalitarian politics” (29). When undesirables could not be eliminated by expulsion, persecutor state devised “final solutions” for such groups seen as obstacles to successful formation of nation-state.
    14. Not just ethnic groups but also religious ones and social strata could be seen as such obstacles.
    15. Arendt: refugees result from transformation of empires and smaller communities into nation-states, taking place historically across wider regions and creating tensions within and between states.
    16. This process of state-formation based on notions of ideological homogeneity started in Europe and eventually extended to the Third World as it underwent decolonization and resulted in countries with even higher ethnic and cultural hetereogenenity as Europe, heightened by social and political inequalities: “integrative revolution” (C. Geertz, 36).
    17. Underdevelopment as key accelerator promoting deployment of increasingly authoritarian strategies to overcome both consolidation of nation-state and underdevelopment itself.
    18. Execution of such strategies results in political persecution of certain categories of the population and causes massive refugee flows. Such tensions encompass entire groups of countries, resulting in interaction between domestic and international conflicts, compounded by intrusion of external powers with an interest in the region.
    19. This is a protracted process that can degenerate into radicalization and even state terrorism, where changes of regime can result in drastic reversals of targets of persecution.
  • Expulsions,  POLS 844: Governing Difference

    Kaufman, C.D. (1998) ‘When all else fails: ethnic population transfers and partitions in the twentieth century’

    Kaufman, C.D. (1998) ‘When all else fails: ethnic population transfers and partitions in the twentieth century’, International Security 23 (2), 120-156.

    Introduction

    1. Separating warrying populations is best solution to many of the worst ethnic conflicts.
    2. Key questions: do partitions and population transfers reduce or increase loss of life?
    3. Move away from integrated multi-ethnic societies in post-conflict situations, as this may promote escalation of violence: separation of warrying groups may dampen conflict.
    4. This remains controversial because of high human costs – only justified if it saves lives of people who would otherwise be killed in ethnic violence.
    5. Key case-studies: Ireland, India, Palestine, Cyprus.
    6. In all four cases, separation of warrying groups reduced subsequent violence, which resulted not from partition / separation but from incompleteness thereof.

    State of Debate

    1. Case for Separation:
      1. Security dilemma: no group can provide for own security without depressing security of others
      2. Power sharing techniques cannot work because they do not resolve such security dilemmas created by mixed demography.
      3. International community should endorse separation for some communal conflicts to avoid much higher human costs.
    2. Case against Separation: Partitions and population transfers have 3 main flaws:
      1. They cause violence;
      2. They generate new conflicts;
      3. They create undemocratic rump states that perpetuate communal hatred.
      4. Therefore, reintegrating ethnic groups in conflict is both more moral and more practical than partition.
    3. This conclusion is wrong because the security dilemma generated by intermixed populations “cannot be stopped except by permanent military occupation or genocide, or by not having the war in the first place” (10).

    Solving the Debate

    1. High-violence partition case studies are best to evaluate effects of international intervention
    2. Four cases: Ireland, India, Palestine, Cyprus.
    3. Ireland:
      1. Violence caused not by partition, but because partition did not fully separate antagonistic communities, especially in the North: fairly intense security dilemmas, in both North and South.
      2. Solution was a better partition line separating the two groups “as fully as possible”, resulting in “a smaller but safer Northern Ireland”.
    4. India and Pakistan:
      1. Security dilemmas created by withdrawal of British imperial power: Muslim / Hindu SD nationally (incl. Kashmir), Muslim / Sikh in Punjab (more severe);
      2. Muslims remaining in India were two few and too dispersed to resist the Indian government (!);
      3. “The problem with Indian independence was not partition, but that partition did not go far enough” (76).
    5. Palestine and Israel
      1. Security dilemmas generated by Israeli independence, not partition.
      2. In 1948 Israel, pattern of ethnic cleansing followed security dilemma logic and varied based on strategic needs of each place and time.
      3. Violence after 1949 was not caused by partition, but by existence of Jewish state.
      4. Settlements in West Bank generated new security dilemma; must be removed.
    6. Cyprus
      1. Stable situation since 1974.
      2. Result of an intense security dilemma.
      3. Turkish invasion “did save thousands who would have been murdered” (97).
    7. Politics of Successor States
      1. Critics of partitions and populations transfers overestimated the risks these “remedies” pose to political development
      2. Democratization
      3. Treatment of ethnic minorities
    8. Challenges for Separation and Partition – Three lessons:
      1. Identify threshold of intergroup violence beyond which we must resort to separation and partition;
      2. Partition should only be undertaken if national communities are or will be separate at the same time: defensible borders are essential.
      3. Refugees from ethnic conflicts should be moved away from threats of massacres and resettled permanently – no return, because this would re-create the security dilemma that triggered the conflict in the first place.